A Treatise on the Theory of Screws

Forfatter: Sir Robert Stawell Ball

År: 1900

Forlag: The University Press

Sted: Cambride

Sider: 544

UDK: 531.1

Søgning i bogen

Den bedste måde at søge i bogen er ved at downloade PDF'en og søge i den.

Derved får du fremhævet ordene visuelt direkte på billedet af siden.

Download PDF

Digitaliseret bog

Bogens tekst er maskinlæst, så der kan være en del fejl og mangler.

Side af 579 Forrige Næste
498 THE THEORY OF SCREWS. rectangular axes. He then attempted to push the body parallel to one of these axes, but it would not stir. He tried to move the body parallel to each of the other axes, but was again unsuccessful. He then attached the body to one of the axes and tried to effect a rotation around that axis. Again he failed, for the constraints were of too elaborate a type to accommodate themselves to Mr Carte- sian’s crude notions. We shall subsequently find that the movements of the body are necessarily of an exquisitely simple type, yet such was the clumsiness and the artificial character of Mr Cartesian’s machinery that he failed to perceive the simplicity. To him it appeared that the body could only move in a highly complex manner; he saw that it could accept a composite movement consisting of rotations about two or three of his axes and simultaneous translations also parallel to two or three axes. Cartesian was a very skilful calculator, and by a series of experiments even with his unsympathetic apparatus he obtained some knowledge of the subject, sufficient for purposes in which a vivid comprehension of the whole was not required. The inadequacy of Cartesian’s geometry was painfully evident when he reported to the committee on the mobility of the rigid body. ‘I find,’ he said, ‘that the body is unable to move parallel to x, or to y, or to a; neither can I make it rotate around x, or y, or z‘, but I could push it an inch parallel to x, pro- vided that at the same time I pushed it a foot parallel to y and a yard backwards parallel to z, and that it was also turned a degree around x, half a degree the other way around y, and twenty-three minutes and nineteen seconds around z.’ ‘Is that all?’ asks the chairman. ‘Oh, no,’ replied Mr Cartesian, ‘there are other proportions in which the ingredients may be combined so as to produce a possible movement,’ and he was proceeding to state them when Mr Commonsense interposed. ‘Stop! stop!’ said he, ‘I can make nothing of all these figures. This jargon about x, y, and z may suffice for your calculations, but it fails to convey to my mind any clear or concise notion of the movements which the body is free to make.’ Many of the committee sympathised with this view of Commonsense, and they came to the conclusion that there was nothing to be extracted from poor old Cartesian and his axes. They felt that there must be some better method, and their hopes of discovering it were raised when they saw Mr Helix volunteer his services and advance to the rigid body. Helix brought with him no cumbrous rectangular axes, but commenced to try the mobility of the body in the simplest manner. He found it lying at rest in a position we may call A. Perceiving that it was in some ways mobile, he gave it a slight displacement to a neighbouring position B. Contrast the procedure of Cartesian with the procedui’e of Helix. Cartesian tried to force the body to move along certain routes which he had arbitrarily chosen, but which the body had not chosen; in fact the body would not take any one of his routes separately, though it would take all of them together in a most embarrassing manner. But Helix had no preconceived scheme as to the nature of the movements to be expected. He simply found the body in a certain position A, and then he coaxed the body to move, not in this particular way or in that particular way, but any way the body liked to any new position B.